Tuesday, March 18, 2014

Baran/Marcuse in current Monthly Review: Fromm's "boot-licking", or critique of 1950s Marcuse's Hegel interpretations?

Monthly Review this month published some of the 1950s-60s correspondence between Marxist philosopher Herbert Marcuse and Left economist, Paul Baran. 

The following quotes a passage from one of Bran's letters to Marcuse, which trashes Erich Fromm's 1961 Marx's Concept of Man. This is followed by Russell Rockwell's contrasting interpretation of Fromm's work, explaining his implicit harsh critique of Marcuse's recent interpretations of Hegel.

From March 1, 2014 Monthly Review
Baran/Marcuse Correspondence

Paul Baran letter to Herbert Marcuse
July 11, 1961
Big Sur, California
Dear Herbert,
...Your remark that even the most ossified Marxism is these days a fountain of truth 

compared with what parades as social science and philosophy was to me a particularly à 

propos since I had just finished reading the Introduction by Fromm to a paperback edition 

of Marx’s Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts (Marx’s Concept of Man, New York, 

1961).14 You must have a look at this thing, if you haven’t yet. This outpouring of 

Fromm’s setzt wirklich dem Fass die Krone [really tops it all off]. After Mr. Strachey and 

Co. have turned the old man into a meritorious—if somewhat confused—predecessor of 

Keynes and Gaitskill, Mr. Fromm promotes him to a follower of Meister Eckhart and to a 

Zen Buddhist thus providing him with the distinction of having anticipated no less a figure 

than Erich Fromm himself.15 On all of the 80 pages of the rubbish that he wrote about 

Marx—in order to acquaint the American public with thoughts of “that great thinker”—

Fromm managed not to mention once the class struggle, not to use once the word 

revolution, not to say anything about the development of the forces of production, about 

antagonistic interests. I don’t think that I have ever read anything as scandalous and at 

the same time as manifestly dishonest. The fellow falsifies outright, misquotes, garbles. 

Even by the current standards the whole thing is an absolute outrage. By the way, since 

he finds it expedient to lick your boots on a couple of occasions, it would be most 

desirable if you reviewed this thing somewhere. Rejecting positivism is one thing, 

sinking into the mud of mysticism is another. And surely there is nothing that is more 

conducive to discrediting Marx in the eyes of such young people who at least potentially 

might begin to understand something than exposing them to the gibberish that Mr. Fromm 

has the temerity to call Marxism.

From Russell Rockwell,  Presentation at November 2013 International Marcuse Conference, Lexington, KY.

It is well-known that in an appendix to his work Eros and Civilization, Marcuse launched a polemic against Fromm’s theory development, including works Fromm had written while both he and Marcuse were still members of the ISR.  For example, Marcuse cites the article, “The Social Conditions of Psychoanalytical Therapy”, Fromm published in the ISR journal in 1935.[1] Marcuse suggests that Fromm begins to argue that happiness can be found within the given society, hence conflating Critical Theory and social conformity. Since the social relevance of Critical Theory resided in its ability to sharpen the edges of psychology and sociology to enhance their critical function, this was indeed a stinging assertion. What might be less well-known is that Marcuse offers high praise for earlier articles Fromm published in 1932-1934. Marcuse argues that there is a fundamental distinction between Fromm’s earlier and later articles. In the earlier ones Fromm demonstrated the “explosive” potential of instinctual structures defined by Freud: when social conditions change to undermine the “patricentric, acquisitive culture”, the functions of instinctual structures change as well—“they cease to be the cement and instead become the dynamite”. [2]
Yet, Marcuse’s critique of the social relevance and trajectory of Fromm’s theory may have served to divert attention from a major change in the trajectory and social relevance of his own theory. And Fromm was eventually to bring this to the attention of his readers in his 1961 work, “Marx’s Concept of Man”. [3] Marcuse’s early 1930s work and many of his writings through Reason and Revolution (where an entire section on the “abolition of labor” was included) clearly suggested the need for a serious reexamination of Hegel’s philosophy. This was in the context of unanswered questions concerning revolutionary praxis, principally labor.
Marcuse’s Eros and Civilization chapter, titled “Philosophical Interlude”, suggested something different. [4] Marcuse indicated Hegel’s continuity with the development of Western philosophy generally, rather than the incorporation and transcendence of this tradition associated with Hegelian-Marxian dialectic. Marcuse, much more so than in his earlier works, conceived Hegel’s Logic as continuous in essential ways with the logic of domination that evolved slowly since Aristotle. [5] In Eros and Civilization, in the context of his development of Freud’s analysis of Western civilization, especially his concepts of the performance and pleasure principles, Marcuse analyzed the evolving idea of reason as historically and increasingly antagonistic to those, “faculties and attitudes that are receptive rather than productive”. [6] Marcuse wrote:
Reason is to ensure, through the ever more effective transformation and exploitation of nature, the fulfillment of human potentialities. But in the process, the ends seem to recede before the means: the time devoted to alienated labor absorbs the time for individual needs—and define the needs themselves. The logos shows forth as the logic of domination…Hegel’s presentation of his system in his Encyclopedia ends on the word ‘enjoys’. The philosophy of  western civilization culminates in the idea that the truth lies in the negation of the principle that governs this civilization—negation in the twofold sense that freedom appears as real only in the idea, and that the endlessly projecting and transcending productivity of being comes to fruition in the perpetual peace of self-conscious receptivity.” [7]
            A section of Fromm‘s 1961 work, Marx’s Concept of Man might be understood as a response to this shift in Marcuse’s theoretical trajectory. It represents a turn-about in the question of the social relevance of Critical Theory, this time of Marcuse’s in place of Fromm’s. In Marx’s Concept of Man (“The Nature of Man”, Part 2 on “Man’s Self-Activity”), Fromm begins by stating that Marx’s concept of man is rooted in Hegel’s thinking. [8] But instead of elaborating on this thought himself, Fromm quotes at length from Marcuse’s Reason and Revolution on Hegel’s Science of Logic, where Marcuse wrote that the task of the dialectical thinker is to, “distinguish the essential from the apparent process of reality and to grasp their relation…the world is an estranged and untrue world so long as man does not destroy its dead objectivity and recognize himself and his own life ‘behind’ the fixed form of things and laws. When he finally wins this self-consciousness, he is on his way not only to the truth of himself, but also of his world. And with the recognition goes the doing. He will try to put this truth into action and make the world what it essentially is, namely, the fulfillment of man’s self-consciousness.” [9]
Thus an interesting aspect of Fromm’s analysis of Hegel’s philosophy in Marx’s Concept of Man is that it refers several times to Marcuse’s Reason and Revolution to support his own versus Marcuse’s position in their debate over Freud’s theories and psychoanalysis at the time of publication of Marcuse’s Eros and Civilization. For example, Fromm interprets the passage (quoted above) from Marcuse in the following: “For Hegel the development of individual powers, capacities and potentialities is possible only by continuous action, never by sheer contemplation or receptivity…In as much as man is not productive, in as much as he is receptive and passive, he is nothing, he is dead. In this productive process, man realizes his own essence, he returns to his own essence.” [10]



[1] Herbert Marcuse, Eros and Civilization, A Philosophical Inquiry into Freud, 1st  Vintage ed. (1955; repr.; New York: Vintage, 1962), 222.
[2] Ibid., 221.
[3] Erich Fromm, Marx’s Concept of Man (1961; repr., New York: Continuum, 1961).
[4] Marcuse, Eros and Civilization, 96-114.
[5] Ibid., 102-103.
[6] Ibid., 101.
[7] Ibid., 101, 105. Compare Marcuse’s analysis of the final paragraph of Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind here with Hegel’s introduction to the Philosophy of Mind, which covers the same ground, though in much more detail. (We analyzed this part of the Introduction in the section above, “Genesis or Dawn—What Happens After?”). In the first of the two paragraphs that comprise the “Subdivision” of the Introduction (385 and 386), Hegel summarizes Mind as Subjective (freedom), Objective (necessity), and Absolute (unity of freedom and necessity). In the final paragraph 386, Hegel intimates that Subjective and Objective Mind (taken up in paragraph 385) are both merely “finite”, and only Absolute Mind is “infinite”. No stronger case can be made than Hegel makes himself here, that he did not ultimately confine “liberation” to thought alone.  Rather, he demonstrated that any theory (and practice) short of freedom’s social realization merely reflects, “A rigid application of finitude by the abstract logician…in dealing with Mind and reason…it is held not a mere matter of logic, but treated also as a moral and religious concern, to adhere to the point of finitude, and the wish to go further is reckoned a mark of audacity, in not of insanity, of thought…philosophy for the concrete forms, has merely to show that the finite is not, i.e. is not the truth, but merely a transition and an emergence to something higher” .
[8] Fromm, Marx’s Concept of Man, 26.
[9] Ibid;, 26-27.
[10] Ibid;, 29-30.

Wednesday, January 22, 2014

2014 Article in Counterpunch on International Marcuse Society Conference, Lexington, KY

The Concrete Distress of Human Existence

Herbert Marcuse and Absolute Struggle in 2013

by JAVIER SETHNESS CASTRO
“One can delineate the domain of philosophy however one likes, but in its search for truth, philosophy is always concerned with human existence.  Authentic philosophizing refuses to remain at the stage of knowledge […].  Care for human existence and its truth makes philosophy a ‘practical science’ in the deepest sense, and it also leads philosophy—and this is the crucial point—into the concrete distress of human existence.”
– Herbert Marcuse, “On Concrete Philosophy” (1929)
[A] major event at the conference was Professor Richard Wolin’s keynote address on “Marcuse and the New Left: Emancipatory Violence as a Problem of Political Philosophy.”  Wolin, author of Heidegger’s Children and co-editor of a collection of Marcuse’s writings from his period of study with Martin Heidegger,Heideggerian Marxism, used his comments to discuss a brief period in the 1960′s when Marcuse is said to have flirted with the concepts of revolutionary violence and of a transitional dictatorship away from capitalism (1964-1968).

According to Wolin, Marcuse must have felt the risks of such a dictatorship to be less than those associated with liberal or Stalinist regimes; the speaker even cited Marcuse’s declaration in Eros and Civilization that, “From Plato to Rousseau, the only honest answer is the idea of an educational dictatorship, exercised by those who are supposed to have acquired knowledge of the real Good.”  Curiously, though, Wolin failed to include Marcuse’s next sentence in his comments refuting the idea: “The answer has since become obsolete: knowledge of the available means for creating a humane existence for all is no longer confined to a privileged elite.”

During the afternoon of the conference’s second day, I attended a panel on “Marcuse, Marx, and Marxisms,”... Russell Rockwell, co-editor of the recently published Dunayevskaya-Marcuse-Fromm Correspondence, 1954-1978 (2013), presented on the trajectories and intersections of the Marxisms advanced by Marcuse and critical psychoanalyst Erich Fromm respectively.  Against established trends which would largely suppress consideration of Fromm’s significant contributions to the nascent Institute for Social Research, Rockwell explained how Fromm felt psychoanalysis could productively serve as a complement to Marxian economism, and he mentioned Fromm’s 1929 lecture to the Institute of Psychoanalysis which cited Marx favorably.  He also brought up Fromm’s 1929 psychological study of workers in Weimar Germany, which was rejected for publication with the Institute for Social Research for practical political considerations—it held that some three-quarters of the German working population would not resist Hitler if he seized power, while only an estimated 15 percent had personality structures which Fromm felt would lead them to actively resist him.  Indeed, the work did not see the light of day for over five decades.  Rockwell stressed that both Fromm and Marcuse shared an interest in the humanism of the young Marx, unlike most of the rest of the theorists associated with the Frankfurt School.

HTTP://WWW.COUNTERPUNCH.ORG/2013/12/16/HERBERT-MARCUSE-AND-ABSOLUTE-STRUGGLE-IN-2013/

Saturday, November 30, 2013

Automation Targeting Even Low-Wage Jobs

This past summer, David H. Autor,  professor of economics at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology and David Dorn, assistant professor of economics at the Center for Monetary and Financial Studies in Madrid, wrote an article in the New York Times, "How Technology Wrecks the Middle Class". Autor has been a primary figure in promoting the thesis that technological changes in the economy are responsible for job market "polarization"-- as employment in routine jobs has ebbed, employment has risen both in high-wage managerial, professional and technical occupations and in low-wage, in-person service occupations:

So computerization is not reducing the quantity of jobs, but rather degrading the quality of jobs for a significant subset of workers. Demand for highly educated workers who excel in abstract tasks is robust, but the middle of the labor market, where the routine task-intensive jobs lie, is sagging. Workers without college education therefore concentrate in manual task-intensive jobs — like food services, cleaning and security — which are numerous but offer low wages, precarious job security and few prospects for upward mobility. This bifurcation of job opportunities has contributed to the historic rise in income inequality.

http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2013/08/24/how-technology-wrecks-the-middle-class/?smid=pl-share

But in a report in the 11/29/13 NYT, "Coming Soon, a Night Watchman With Wheels", science writer John Markoff, writes:

A company in California has developed a mobile robot, known as the K5Autonomous Data Machine, as a safety and security tool for corporations, as well as for schools and neighborhoods...The night watchman of the future is 5 feet tall, weighs 300 pounds and looks a lot like R2-D2 – without the whimsy. And will work for $6.25 an hour.
And the addition of such a machine to the labor market could force David Autor, Massachusetts Institute of Technology economist, to rethink his theory about how technology wrecks the middle class.
The minimum wage in the United States is $7.25, and $8 in California. Coming in substantially under those costs, Knightscope’s robot watchman service raises questions about whether artificial intelligence and robotics technologies are beginning to assault both the top and the bottom of the work force as well.
 Over all, there are about 1.3 million private security guards in the United States, and they are low paid for the most part, averaging about $23,000 a year, according to the Service Employees International Union. Most are not unionized, so they are vulnerable to low-cost automation alternatives.
http://www.nytimes.com/2013/12/03/science/coming-soon-a-night-watchman-with-wheels.html?smid=pl-share




Thursday, October 31, 2013

Special Double Issue of Radical Philosophy Review on Herbert Marcuse

CRITICAL REFUSALS
Special Double Issue

Radical Philosophy Review, Volume 16, Number 1 (2013)
Radical Philosophy Review, Volume 16, Number 2 (2013)
Andrew T. Lamas, General Editor and Coeditor
Arnold L. Farr, Douglas Kellner, and Charles Reitz, Coeditors
Caroline Cohn, Associate Editor

Includes Russell Rockwell Marcuse's Hegelian Marxism, Marx's Grundrisse, Hegel's Dialectic


http://eepurl.com/HXtHL

See also announcement of draft manuscript of Marcuse's One-Dimensional Man discovered in the Goldfarb library at Brandeis University

http://www.brandeis.edu/now/2013/october/marcuse.html

Monday, October 14, 2013

2013 International Herbert Marcuse Society Conference: Russell Rockwell on Marcuse's and Fromm's Marxism

Friday, November 8, University of Kentucky, Lexington

2:15pm-3:45pm Session 3: Concurrent 

Student Center, Room 249

Panel 8: Marcuse, Marx, and Marxisms

Fred Mecklenburg Marx’s Marxism: A New Attitude to Objectivity

David M. Peña-Guzman The Marxism-Heideggerianism Tension: A Philosophical Disjunction

Karla Encalada Falconi Marx and Lacan: The Comparison of the Impossible

Russell Rockwell Marcuse’s and Fromm’s Marxism: Their Trajectories, Intersections, and Social Relevance

http://www.scribd.com/doc/175978030/2013-Marcuse-Program-rev-10-11-2013-1pm-1